Transposition (logic)
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
propositional logic Propositional calculus is a branch of logic. It is also called propositional logic, statement logic, sentential calculus, sentential logic, or sometimes zeroth-order logic. It deals with propositions (which can be true or false) and relations b ...
, transposition is a valid
rule of replacement In logic, a rule of replacementMoore and Parker is a transformation rule that may be applied to only a particular segment of an logical expression, expression. A logical system may be constructed so that it uses either axioms, rules of inference ...
that permits one to switch the antecedent with the
consequent A consequent is the second half of a hypothetical proposition. In the standard form of such a proposition, it is the part that follows "then". In an implication, if ''P'' implies ''Q'', then ''P'' is called the antecedent and ''Q'' is called ...
of a conditional statement in a logical proof if they are also both negated. It is the
inference Inferences are steps in reasoning, moving from premises to logical consequences; etymologically, the word '' infer'' means to "carry forward". Inference is theoretically traditionally divided into deduction and induction, a distinction that in ...
from the truth of "''A'' implies ''B''" to the truth of "Not-''B'' implies not-''A''", and conversely. It is very closely related to the rule of inference
modus tollens In propositional logic, ''modus tollens'' () (MT), also known as ''modus tollendo tollens'' (Latin for "method of removing by taking away") and denying the consequent, is a deductive argument form and a rule of inference. ''Modus tollens' ...
. It is the rule that (P \to Q) \Leftrightarrow (\neg Q \to \neg P) where "\Leftrightarrow" is a
metalogic Metalogic is the study of the metatheory of logic. Whereas ''logic'' studies how logical systems can be used to construct valid and sound arguments, metalogic studies the properties of logical systems.Harry GenslerIntroduction to Logic Routledge, ...
al
symbol A symbol is a mark, sign, or word that indicates, signifies, or is understood as representing an idea, object, or relationship. Symbols allow people to go beyond what is known or seen by creating linkages between otherwise very different conc ...
representing "can be replaced in a proof with".


Formal notation

The ''transposition'' rule may be expressed as a
sequent In mathematical logic, a sequent is a very general kind of conditional assertion. : A_1,\,\dots,A_m \,\vdash\, B_1,\,\dots,B_n. A sequent may have any number ''m'' of condition formulas ''Ai'' (called " antecedents") and any number ''n'' of asse ...
: :(P \to Q) \vdash (\neg Q \to \neg P) where \vdash is a metalogical symbol meaning that (\neg Q \to \neg P) is a
syntactic consequence Logical consequence (also entailment) is a fundamental concept in logic, which describes the relationship between statement (logic), statements that hold true when one statement logically ''follows from'' one or more statements. A Validity (lo ...
of (P \to Q) in some logical system; or as a rule of inference: :\frac where the rule is that wherever an instance of "P \to Q" appears on a line of a proof, it can be replaced with "\neg Q \to \neg P"; or as the statement of a truth-functional tautology or
theorem In mathematics, a theorem is a statement that has been proved, or can be proved. The ''proof'' of a theorem is a logical argument that uses the inference rules of a deductive system to establish that the theorem is a logical consequence of th ...
of propositional logic. The principle was stated as a theorem of propositional logic by Russell and Whitehead in ''
Principia Mathematica The ''Principia Mathematica'' (often abbreviated ''PM'') is a three-volume work on the foundations of mathematics written by mathematician–philosophers Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell and published in 1910, 1912, and 1913. ...
'' as: :(P \to Q) \to (\neg Q \to \neg P) where P and Q are propositions expressed in some
formal system A formal system is an abstract structure used for inferring theorems from axioms according to a set of rules. These rules, which are used for carrying out the inference of theorems from axioms, are the logical calculus of the formal system. A form ...
.


Traditional logic


Form of transposition

In the inferred proposition, the consequent is the contradictory of the antecedent in the original proposition, and the antecedent of the inferred proposition is the contradictory of the consequent of the original proposition. The symbol for material implication signifies the proposition as a hypothetical, or the "if-then" form, e.g. "if P then Q". The biconditional statement of the rule of transposition (↔) refers to the relation between hypothetical (→) ''propositions'', with each proposition including an antecent and consequential term. As a matter of logical inference, to transpose or convert the terms of one proposition requires the conversion of the terms of the propositions on both sides of the biconditional relationship. Meaning, to transpose or convert (P → Q) to (Q → P) requires that the other proposition, (~Q → ~P), be transposed or converted to (~P → ~Q). Otherwise, to convert the terms of one proposition and not the other renders the rule invalid, violating the
sufficient condition In logic and mathematics, necessity and sufficiency are terms used to describe a conditional or implicational relationship between two statements. For example, in the conditional statement: "If then ", is necessary for , because the truth of ...
and
necessary condition In logic and mathematics, necessity and sufficiency are terms used to describe a conditional or implicational relationship between two statements. For example, in the conditional statement: "If then ", is necessary for , because the truth of ...
of the terms of the propositions, where the violation is that the changed proposition commits the fallacy of
denying the antecedent Denying the antecedent, sometimes also called inverse error or fallacy of the inverse, is a formal fallacy of inferring the inverse from the original statement. It is committed by reasoning in the form: :If ''P'', then ''Q''. :Therefore, if not ...
or
affirming the consequent Affirming the consequent, sometimes called converse error, fallacy of the converse, or confusion of necessity and sufficiency, is a formal fallacy of taking a true conditional statement (e.g., "If the lamp were broken, then the room would be dar ...
by means of illicit
conversion Conversion or convert may refer to: Arts, entertainment, and media * "Conversion" (''Doctor Who'' audio), an episode of the audio drama ''Cyberman'' * "Conversion" (''Stargate Atlantis''), an episode of the television series * "The Conversion" ...
. The truth of the rule of transposition is dependent upon the relations of sufficient condition and necessary condition in logic.


Sufficient condition

In the proposition "If P then Q", the occurrence of 'P' is sufficient reason for the occurrence of 'Q'. 'P', as an individual or a class, materially implicates 'Q', but the relation of 'Q' to 'P' is such that the converse proposition "If Q then P" does not necessarily have sufficient condition. The rule of inference for sufficient condition is ''modus ponens'', which is an argument for conditional implication: # Premise (1): If P, then Q # Premise (2): P # Conclusion: Therefore, Q


Necessary condition

Since the converse of premise (1) is not valid, all that can be stated of the relationship of 'P' and 'Q' is that in the absence of 'Q', 'P' does not occur, meaning that 'Q' is the necessary condition for 'P'. The rule of inference for necessary condition is ''modus tollens'': # Premise (1): If P, then Q # Premise (2): not Q # Conclusion: Therefore, not P


Necessity and sufficiency example

An example traditionally used by logicians contrasting sufficient and necessary conditions is the statement "If there is fire, then oxygen is present". An oxygenated environment is necessary for fire or combustion, but simply because there is an oxygenated environment does not necessarily mean that fire or combustion is occurring. While one can infer that fire stipulates the presence of oxygen, from the presence of oxygen the converse "If there is oxygen present, then fire is present" cannot be inferred. All that can be inferred from the original proposition is that "If oxygen is not present, then there cannot be fire".


Relationship of propositions

The symbol for the biconditional ("↔") signifies the relationship between the propositions is both necessary and sufficient, and is verbalized as "
if and only if In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (shortened as "iff") is a biconditional logical connective between statements, where either both statements are true or both are false. The connective is bicondi ...
", or, according to the example "If P then Q 'if and only if' if not Q then not P". Necessary and sufficient conditions can be explained by analogy in terms of the concepts and the rules of immediate inference of traditional logic. In the categorical proposition "All S is P", the subject term 'S' is said to be distributed, that is, all members of its class are exhausted in its expression. Conversely, the predicate term 'P' cannot be said to be distributed, or exhausted in its expression because it is indeterminate whether every instance of a member of 'P' as a class is also a member of 'S' as a class. All that can be validly inferred is that "Some P are S". Thus, the type 'A' proposition "All P is S" cannot be inferred by conversion from the original 'A' type proposition "All S is P". All that can be inferred is the type "A" proposition "All non-P is non-S" (Note that (P → Q) and (~Q → ~P) are both 'A' type propositions). Grammatically, one cannot infer "all mortals are men" from "All men are mortal". An 'A' type proposition can only be immediately inferred by conversion when both the subject and predicate are distributed, as in the inference "All bachelors are unmarried men" from "All unmarried men are bachelors".


Transposition and the method of contraposition

In
traditional logic In philosophy, term logic, also known as traditional logic, syllogistic logic or Aristotelian logic, is a loose name for an approach to formal logic that began with Aristotle and was developed further in ancient history mostly by his followers, ...
the reasoning process of transposition as a rule of inference is applied to
categorical propositions In logic, a categorical proposition, or categorical statement, is a proposition that asserts or denies that all or some of the members of one category (the ''subject term'') are included in another (the ''predicate term''). The study of arguments ...
through
contraposition In logic and mathematics, contraposition refers to the inference of going from a conditional statement into its logically equivalent contrapositive, and an associated proof method known as Proof by contrapositive, proof by contraposition. The cont ...
and
obversion In traditional logic, obversion is a "type of immediate inference in which from a given proposition another proposition is inferred whose subject is the same as the original subject, whose predicate is the contradictory of the original predicate, ...
, a series of immediate inferences where the rule of obversion is first applied to the original categorical proposition "All S is P"; yielding the obverse "No S is non-P". In the obversion of the original proposition to an 'E' type proposition, both terms become distributed. The obverse is then converted, resulting in "No non-P is S", maintaining distribution of both terms. The No non-P is S" is again obverted, resulting in the ontrapositive"All non-P is non-S". Since nothing is said in the definition of contraposition with regard to the predicate of the inferred proposition, it is permissible that it could be the original subject or its contradictory, and the predicate term of the resulting 'A' type proposition is again undistributed. This results in two contrapositives, one where the predicate term is distributed, and another where the predicate term is undistributed.


Differences between transposition and contraposition

Note that the method of transposition and contraposition should not be confused. Contraposition is a type of
immediate inference An immediate inference is an inference which can be made from only one statement or proposition. For instance, from the statement "All toads are green", the immediate inference can be made that "no toads are not green" or "no toads are non-green" ...
in which from a given categorical proposition another categorical proposition is inferred which has as its subject the contradictory of the original predicate. Since nothing is said in the definition of contraposition with regard to the predicate of the inferred proposition, it is permissible that it could be the original subject or its contradictory. This is in contradistinction to the form of the propositions of transposition, which may be material implication, or a hypothetical statement. The difference is that in its application to categorical propositions the result of contraposition is two contrapositives, each being the obvert of the other, i.e. "No non-P is S" and "All non-P is non-S". The distinction between the two contrapositives is absorbed and eliminated in the principle of transposition, which presupposes the "mediate inferences" of contraposition and is also referred to as the "law of contraposition".Prior, A.N. "Logic, Traditional". ''Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', Vol.5, Macmillan, 1973.


Transposition in mathematical logic


Proofs


In classical propositional calculus system

In Hilbert-style deductive systems for propositional logic, only one side of the transposition is taken as an axiom, and the other is a theorem. We describe a proof of this theorem in the system of three axioms proposed by
Jan Łukasiewicz Jan Łukasiewicz (; 21 December 1878 – 13 February 1956) was a Polish logician and philosopher who is best known for Polish notation and Łukasiewicz logic His work centred on philosophical logic, mathematical logic and history of logic. He ...
: :A1. \phi \to \left( \psi \to \phi \right) :A2. \left( \phi \to \left( \psi \rightarrow \xi \right) \right) \to \left( \left( \phi \to \psi \right) \to \left( \phi \to \xi \right) \right) :A3. \left ( \lnot \phi \to \lnot \psi \right) \to \left( \psi \to \phi \right) (A3) already gives one of the directions of the transposition. The other side, ( \psi \to \phi ) \to ( \neg \phi \to \neg \psi), if proven below, using the following lemmas proven
here Here is an adverb that means "in, on, or at this place". It may also refer to: Software * Here Technologies, a mapping company * Here WeGo (formerly Here Maps), a mobile app and map website by Here Technologies, Here Television * Here TV (form ...
: : (DN1) \neg \neg p \to p -
Double negation In propositional logic, double negation is the theorem that states that "If a statement is true, then it is not the case that the statement is not true." This is expressed by saying that a proposition ''A'' is logically equivalent to ''not (not ...
(one direction) : (DN2) p \to \neg \neg p - Double negation (another direction) : (HS1) (q \to r) \to ((p \to q) \to (p \to r)) - one form of
Hypothetical syllogism In classical logic, a hypothetical syllogism is a valid argument form, a syllogism with a conditional statement for one or both of its premises. An example in English: :If I do not wake up, then I cannot go to work. :If I cannot go to work, then ...
: (HS2) (p \to q) \to ((q \to r) \to (p \to r)) - another form of Hypothetical syllogism. We also use the method of the hypothetical syllogism metatheorem as a shorthand for several proof steps. The proof is as follows: :(1) q \to \neg\neg q       (instance of the (DN2)) :(2) (q \to \neg\neg q) \to ((p \to q) \to (p \to \neg\neg q))       (instance of the (HS1) :(3) (p \to q) \to (p \to \neg\neg q)       (from (1) and (2) by modus ponens) :(4) \neg\neg p \to p       (instance of the (DN1)) :(5) (\neg\neg p \to p) \to ((p \to \neg\neg q) \to (\neg\neg p \to \neg\neg q))       (instance of the (HS2)) :(6) (p \to \neg\neg q) \to (\neg\neg p \to \neg\neg q)       (from (4) and (5) by modus ponens) :(7) (p \to q) \to (\neg\neg p \to \neg\neg q)       (from (3) and (6) using the hypothetical syllogism metatheorem) :(8) (\neg\neg p \to \neg\neg q) \to (\neg q \to \neg p)       (instance of (A3)) :(9) (p \to q) \to (\neg q \to \neg p)       (from (7) and (8) using the hypothetical syllogism metatheorem)


See also

*
Contraposition (traditional logic) In traditional logic, contraposition is a form of immediate inference in which a proposition is inferred from another and where the former has for its subject the contradictory of the original logical proposition's predicate. In some cases, contra ...
*
Syllogism A syllogism ( grc-gre, συλλογισμός, ''syllogismos'', 'conclusion, inference') is a kind of logical argument that applies deductive reasoning to arrive at a conclusion based on two propositions that are asserted or assumed to be true. ...
*
Term logic In philosophy, term logic, also known as traditional logic, syllogistic logic or Aristotelian logic, is a loose name for an approach to formal logic that began with Aristotle and was developed further in ancient history mostly by his followers, th ...


References


Further reading

*Brody, Bobuch A. "Glossary of Logical Terms". Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 5-6, p. 61. Macmillan, 1973. * *Copi, Irving. ''Symbolic Logic''. MacMillan, 1979, fifth edition. *Prior, A.N. "Logic, Traditional". ''Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', Vol. 5, Macmillan, 1973. * Stebbing, Susan. ''A Modern Introduction to Logic''. Harper, 1961, Seventh edition


External links


Improper Transposition
(Fallacy Files) {{DEFAULTSORT:Transposition (Logic) Rules of inference Theorems in propositional logic